This is one in a series of blog posts in which I discuss some of the concepts and terminology that I forward in my
writings, including my recent book Excluded: Making Feminist and Queer Movements More Inclusive.
In Excluded, I argue
that instead of focusing on only one or a few forms of sexism and
marginalization, we should acknowledge that there are myriad double standards out there. And given this, it is crucial for us to more generally recognize and
challenge double standards whenever and wherever they occur.
To be honest, I think that we as activists tend not to be
very good at doing this—it is a main reason why people who are quite familiar
with one particular form of marginalization (typically one that they are
personally impacted by) will nevertheless continue to single out and invalidate
other groups of people, often using the exact same tactics that they abhor when
used against members of their own group. In other words, a failure to recognize
and understand how double standards function in a general sense is what enables
various forms of exclusion to run rampant within our movements. It is also what
enables numerous forms of sexism and marginalization to proliferate in society
at large.
I discuss this issue over the course of Excluded, but I address it head on in Chapter 14: “How Double
Standards Work”—it is one of the pieces of writing that I am most proud of.
In both these examples (and I would argue, in double
standards more generally), the marked groups are considered to be inherently
remarkable and questionable, which is why people have to “come out” as trans or
gay or bi, but not as cisgender or heterosexual. It is why trans and queer folks
are subjected to all sorts of commentary and debate that our cis and hetero
counterparts never have to deal with. It is why we are often mischaracterized
as abnormal, artificial and deceptive, and why we are often viewed as alien or exotic.
As I put it in Excluded:
Essentially, people
who are marked are generally viewed as “having something” that unmarked people
do not have. That “something” can therefore be subjected to remarks, questions,
debate, praise or critique; the unmarked person escapes such critical analysis
by virtue of the fact that they are not seen as having that “something.”
[p.178]
For the record, I did not invent the concept of marked
versus unmarked. As I say in the Notes section of the book:
The concept of marked
versus unmarked originated in the field of linguistics, but has since been
applied to semiotics (the study of signs and symbols), sociology, and related
fields. See Wayne Brekhus, “A Sociology of the Unmarked,” Sociological Theory
16, no. 1 (1998), 34-51; Linda R. Waugh,
“Marked and unmarked: A choice between unequals in semiotic structure,”
Semiotica 38 (1982), 299-318. This
chapter is my own personal take on the unmarked/marked distinction and how it
creates obstacles and double binds for members of marginalized groups.
[p.316]
I decided to articulate double standards in terms of the
unmarked/marked distinction because it elegantly explains why marginalization
can be so effective and pervasive. Basically, when a group is marked, it is as
if they become “sticky,” in that all sorts of assumptions, meanings,
stereotypes, invalidations, etc., will “stick” to them, but not to the unmarked
majority.
Why do we mark some
people and not others?
This question came up a lot when I was doing book readings
for Excluded. Some people may be
looking for a “Back when our ancestors were living on the plains of Africa...”
type of answer, but I am not a big fan of such evolutionary psychology-type handwaving. What I
can say is that this phenomenon seems to be fueled by certain general
perceptual biases that people have. For instance, social psychologists have
found that we tend to perceive outgroup members (that is, people who we see as
different from us in a fundamental way) more negatively, more extremely, and in
a more stereotyped manner than we do members of our ingroup. We also tend to
pay more attention to unexpected people or traits, and to view them more
negatively, than people or traits that we consider to be expected or mundane.
Together, these perceptual biases may lead us to mark people who we view as “other”
for whatever reason.
Having said that, it is not simply the case that we are
“programmed” to mark unexpected or atypical people. As I point out in the book,
even though women constitute a slight majority of the population, we are
nevertheless marked relative to men in our culture. And while the number of
certified public accountants in the U.S. is roughly similar to the number of
trans people (in both cases, roughly 0.2% of the population), trans people are
clearly marked in our culture whereas accountants are not. So in other words,
we are taught to mark certain types of people or behaviors—to view them as
remarkable, unusual, exotic, potentially suspect, etc.—while viewing others as
unmarked.
It is also important to recognize that marking people is an
active process: When we look upon the world, we are constantly making decisions
and determinations about whether the individuals that we see seem remarkable or
unremarkable to us. But because this process generally occurs on an unconscious
level, we tend not to notice it as an active process on our part, and instead
we mistakenly assume that the marked individual is inherently noteworthy.
However, the fact that marking occurs at the level of perception or
interpretation becomes evident when we consider the fact that who is deemed marked
varies from perceiver to perceiver. For instance, many people in our culture
mark trans people (while deeming cis people unmarked), whereas I personally
don’t consider trans people to be inherently remarkable, unusual, exotic,
potentially suspect, etc.—after all, I am trans and many of my friends are
trans, so to me trans folks and experiences are an ordinary part of my everyday
life.
Is marking someone the
same thing as marginalizing them?
In Excluded, I
make the case that unmarked/marked distinction plays a fundamental role in all
forms of marginalization. In each case, the marked group is unfairly singled
out and plagued by assumptions and stereotypes that the unmarked group does not
face. This is why activist movements often work to name the unmarked majority
(e.g., those who are heterosexual, cisgender, monosexual, white, able-bodied,
etc.) and point out the many privileges they experience (many of which are
directly related to them *not* being viewed as inherently remarkable,
questionable, abnormal, artificial, deceptive, and/or exotic). To be clear, I
am not insinuating that all forms of marginalization are the same—they each
have different histories, they are institutionalized in different ways, they
employ different assumptions and stereotypes, and so on. But recognizing the
parallels between how marked/marginalized groups are viewed is an important
tool for us as activists.
It should be pointed out that a person can be marked without
being marginalized. Specifically, while some marked groups are stigmatized (as is the case for most
marginalized groups), others may be glorified.
Examples of the latter may include celebrities or people of considerable wealth
or power. Because they are marked, people in these latter categories may be
viewed as extraordinary and exotic, attract a lot of attention, garner
commentary (in the form of praise and/or critiques), and others may consider it
OK to invade their privacy. These are all potentially negative aspects of being
marked, although it would be incorrect to say that such individuals are
marginalized (as they are marked for supposedly being “better than” the unmarked majority, not “lesser than”).
How does
understanding the unmarked/marked distinction help us to become better
activists?
Recognizing the hallmarks of double standards may allow us
to more readily appreciate and learn to challenge forms of sexism and marginalization
that we are less familiar with. In the talk I previously mentioned, I have found
that my describing the parallels between cissexism and heterosexism in terms of
the unmarked/marked distinction has been quite productive in getting audiences
to recognize and appreciate cissexism. It helps them to see how being marked
(for whatever reason) can lead to a predictable set of negative consequences,
rather than them having to reimagine cissexism as a completely novel form of
marginalization unlike anything that they were previously familiar with.
One of the most useful aspects of understanding the
unmarked/marked distinction is that it allows us to become familiar with the
numerous double-binds that plague marked/marginalized groups. In the chapter
“How Double Standards Work,” I discuss some of the most prevalent of such
double binds: invisible/visible, credit/detriment, disavow/identify,
accommodating/angry, afflicted/chosen, dupes/fakes, ashamed/shameless, harmless/dangerous,
pass/reveal.
To give you an idea of what I mean by double-bind, here is
an excerpt from the passage regarding the accommodating/angry double-bind:
When we are marked,
other people feel entitled to pay undue attention to, remark about, and call
into question that aspect of our being. Such incidents can range from being
slightly annoying to downright invalidating. When we are constantly being put
into question like this, there are two general types of responses we might
take. The first is to accommodate these actions. For instance, if people are
staring at us, we just put it out of our minds. If people make remarks about
us, we do not object. If people ask us questions, we politely answer them. This
approach can be highly disempowering, as it places us on the defensive and
perpetuates the idea that others are entitled to constantly call our marked
trait into question, and that it’s our job to accommodate them.
The alternative, of
course, is to challenge other people when they mark us. So if they stare at us,
we tell them that it’s impolite to stare, or stare back at them. If they remark
about us, we call them out on their comments. If they ask us questions, we
remind them of how invasive it is to be interrogated like that. On the positive
side, these are proactive approaches that challenge the double standard. But
the problem is, the fact that we’ve been deemed marked means that they feel
entitled to call us into question. So in their minds, it is we who are acting
inappropriately, and they will likely interpret our righteous responses as an
attack on them. Often they will interpret us as acting “angry,” even if we
challenge them in a polite manner without ever raising our voice.
Understanding these double-binds allows us to see the
futility of many one-size-fits-all approaches to activism that perpetually
arise within our movements. For instance, more “liberal” voices within our
movements may insist that we should act polite in our dealings with the
dominant majority, while more “radical” voices may insist that we should be in
their face and not let them trample all over us. But the reality is that
neither reaction fundamentally addresses the core problem—i.e., the fact that marginalized
individuals are marked and therefore viewed and treated differently. Another
example I discuss in the chapter is how some of the approaches taken by both
“sex-negative” and “sex-positive” feminists with regard to the virgin/whore
double-bind (which I describe as an instance of the more general ashamed/shameless double-bind) do not
actually address the core problem: that in our culture, women’s bodies and
sexualities are marked relative to men’s.
The take home point is this: Those of us who are
marked/marginalized may react differently to the double standards we face.
Insisting that we as individuals should all react to instances of
marginalization the same way will not address the primary problem—in fact, it
will ultimately lead to exclusive movements. So rather than policing how marked/marginalized
individuals respond to their particular circumstances, we should instead focus
our efforts on challenging the primary act, which is our tendency to mark certain people and view/treat them differently from others. While this can
certainly happen at the level of specific marginalized groups (e.g., trans
activists challenging how trans people are marked in our society), I believe
that it is crucial that we more generally raise awareness about the
unmarked/marked distinction and how it creates double standards and
double-binds in many people’s lives. I discuss this more general approach to challenging double standards in far greater detail in Excluded.
[note: If you appreciate this essay and want to see more like it, please check out my Patreon page]
[note: If you appreciate this essay and want to see more like it, please check out my Patreon page]
I'm curious how you view being marked in relation to being invisible. You say that being marked is the reason that people have to "come out", but what about prior to coming out? If someone hasn't come out (to others or to themselves), it would seem that they have not yet been marked. And yet, it's considered a good thing to come out, to go from unmarked to marked. This seems at odds with the idea that being marked is a fundamental part of marginalization.
ReplyDeleteSo one of the double-binds that marked groups face (and which I discuss more in depth in this chapter of Excluded) is the invisible/visible double-bind. There are both potential advantages & disadvantages to each side of this double-bind.
DeleteSo for instance, I am a trans person, and trans people are marked in our society. I am often read as cis by other people - when this happens, I am invisible, which simply means that I am not recognized as a member of a marked group. But I am nevertheless marked. And as soon as I out myself or am discovered to be trans, I will become visible, which means that people will recognize me and treat me as marked.
The disadvantages of being visible are obvious (e.g., I may face transphobia), but being invisible has disadvantages too (e.g., having to manage other people's expectations that I am cis, and possibly being accused of "deceiving" people if I am found out).
So being marked is not the same thing as being visible. People are either visibly marked, or their marked status is invisible (yet still there). I hope that makes sense.
People don't have the right to know your "marked" status. If one believes that they might as well announce it publicly and humiliate themselves. It's degrading to believe that you are deceiving people by withholding information they do not have the right to know.
ReplyDeleteI would no sooner announce I have cancer, an STD, or I just won the mega millions lottery.
I present as the gender I am. The only ones that have a right to know what I am genetically are people I am intimate with.